And now onto the last serious topic, one even more basic than Peano arithmetic. The axiom system we'll be using for set theory is ZFC (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice).
1Set Theory¶
1.1Notation¶
The ∑ signature for this system is {∈} which is a binary relation symbol and that's it.
We often will write x∉X instead of ¬(x∈X)
x⊆y abbreviates ∀z(z∈x→z∈y). ⊆ is read as "is a subset of". ⊂, on the other hand, means "is a proper subset of" and does not include the possibility that x and y are the same set. We won't be using
1.2Russell's paradox¶
Consider the set R={x:x∉X} is R∈R? This is called Russell's paradox.
If yes then R∉R but then... contradiction.
The usual way out of this paradox: R is not a set.
1.3Axioms of Set Theory¶
Most axioms of set theory are constructive principles, for making sets.
1.3.1Extensionality¶
∀x∀y(∀z(z∈x⟺z∈y)→x=y) (a set is completely defined by what things it has as elements)
We can also write extensionality as ∀x∀y(x=y↔(x⊂y∧y⊂x)).
Note that extensionality tells us something about the nature of sets, but doesn't actually give us any. The next axiom does, however.
1.3.2Empty set axiom¶
∃x∀y(y∉x) (there is a set that has no elements)
This is called the empty set, which can be defined as follows: ∅={y:y≠y)={}. By extensionality, there is only one such set.
1.3.3Comprehension (separation) scheme¶
The sweeping construction principle.
Let Φ(x,ˉy) be the Σ-formula ∀y(y∉x). We then have the following axiom:
∀ˉy[∀z(∃w∀x(x∈w⟺(x∈z∧Φ(x,ˉy)))]
In other words, there must be a set z that is "bigger" than w1. But we need z firstwhat?.
N.B. for all x,y,z:
- x⊆x
- x⊆y∧y⊆z→x=y
- x⊆y∧y⊆z→x⊆z
- ∅⊆x
- x⊆∅⟺x=∅
1.3.4Pairing¶
∀x∀y∃z(x∈z∧y∈z) (note: x and y can be equal)
Accepting this, we can now show the existence of a set Z such that ∅∈Z.
In fact, an instance of comprehension now gives us {∅} - the set composed of only the empty set - which we can think of as the number "1" (with the empty set being the number "0"). Φ(x) in this case is ∀u(u∈x).what does this mean?
Now that we have two things to play with, let's make more! But first, let's look at singletons:
1.3.5Singletons¶
A singleton x ({x}) is the set with only x as an element.
A "doubleton x,y" is {x,y} where x≠y.
We can now form some more sets: {{∅}} from before, and {∅,{∅}} ("2", as it has two elements). Or, {1} and {0,1}.
Now, we would like to get {0,1,2}=3 but we can't yet make a set with three elements, as pairing doesn't guarantee us anything beyond "2". We can form {0,1} and {2}, but because we don't have any sort of "union" axiom yet, we can't really do anything with that.
1.3.6Intersections¶
We can, however, form an axiom for intersections. We define z∩y as the set w={x∈z:x∈y}, where Φ(x,y) is x∈y.
We can also form z∖y: {x∈z:x∉y.
1.3.7Unions¶
(Not the kind that likes to go on strike, the other kind)
∀x∃y(∀z∀w(z∈w∧w∈x→z∈y)) (so y is the union of all the x's - ⋃x
We can now form finite and infinite sets. If the sets in x are z1,z2,z3,… then ⋃x=z1∪z2∪…. A∪B=⋃{A,B}; 3=∪{{0,1},{2}}. We can also form 4, 5, 6 etc.
-
As Russell's paradox demonstrates, some care needs to be taken about accepting the "set" {,xΦ(x)}. This isn't really relevant though. ↩